170x Filetype PDF File size 0.08 MB Source: math24.files.wordpress.com
Folland: Real Analysis, Chapter 1 S´ebastien Picard Problem 1.5 If M is the σ-algebra generated by E, then M is the union of the σ-algebras generated by F as F ranges over all countable subsets of E. (Hint: Show that the latter object is a σ-algebra.) Solution: Let N denote the union of the σ-algebras generated by F as F ranges over all count- able subsets of E. N = [ M(F): F⊂E; F countable When F ⊂ E, the σ-algebra generated by F is contained in the σ-algebra generated by E ie M(F)⊂M(E)=M,sowehaveN ⊂M. For the reverse containement, we first observe that E ⊂ N. Indeed, if E = {A } where J α α∈J is some index set, then E ⊂ [M({A })⊂N: α α∈J Next, we will show that N is a σ-algebra. Since M(E) is the smallest σ-algebra containing E, we will have M = M(E) ⊂ N and this will complete the proof. c Let A ∈ N. Then A ∈ M(F) for some countable F ⊂ E. Therefore A ∈ M(F) ⊂ N. Next, ∞ ∞ consider ∪ A where A ∈ N. Then each A ∈ M(F ) for some countable F ⊂ E. Since ∪ F is i=1 i i i i i j=1 j ∞ ∞ ∞ countable, we have A ∈ M(∪ F ) ⊂ N for each A . Hence ∪ A ∈M(∪ F)⊂N. i j=1 j i i=1 i j=1 j Problem 1.12 Let (X;M;µ) be a finite measure space. a. If E;F ∈ M and µ(E∆F) = 0, then µ(E) = µ(F). b. Say that E ∼ F if µ(E∆F) = 0; then ∼ is an equivalence relation on M. c. For E;F ∈ M, define ρ(E;F) = µ(E∆F). Then ρ(E;G) ≤ ρ(E;F)+ρ(F;G), and hence ρ defines a metric on the space M= ∼ of equivalence classes. Solution: (a) First, notice 0 = µ(E∆F)=µ(E\F ∪ F\E)=µ(E\F)+µ(F\E): Hence µ(E\F) = µ(F\E) = 0. It follows that µ(E) = µ(E\F)+µ(E∩F)=µ(E∩F); 1 µ(F) = µ(F\E)+µ(F ∩E)=µ(E∩F): Therefore, µ(E) = µ(F). (b) It is clear that ∼ is reflexive: µ(E∆E) = µ(∅) = 0. It is also easy to see that ∼ is symmetric: if E∼F,thenµ(E∆F)=µ(F∆E)=0,soF ∼E. It only remains to show that ∼ is transitive. Suppose E ∼ F and F ∼ G. Then µ(E ∩ Fc) + µ(Fc∩E)=0andµ(F ∩Gc)+µ(Fc∩G)=0. Therefore, µ(E∆G)=µ(E∩Gc)+µ(Ec∩G) =µ(E∩Gc∩Fc)+µ(Ec∩G∩F)+µ(E∩Gc∩F)+µ(Ec∩G∩Fc) ≤µ(E∩Fc)+µ(Ec∩F)+µ(F ∩Gc)+µ(Fc∩G) =0+0=0: Since µ(E∆G) ≥ 0, we must have µ(E∆G) = 0. (c) We show the triangle inequality. Given E;F;G ∈ M, then ρ(E;G) = µ(E∆G) =µ(E∩Gc∩Fc)+µ(E∩Gc∩F)+µ(G∩Ec∩F)+µ(G∩Ec∩Fc) =(µ(E∩Gc∩Fc)+µ(E∩G∩Fc)+µ(F∩Gc∩Ec)+µ(F ∩G∩Ec)) +(µ(F ∩Gc∩Ec)+µ(F ∩Gc∩E)+µ(G∩Ec∩Fc)+µ(G∩E∩Fc)): =ρ(E∆F)+µ(F∆G)=ρ(E;F)+ρ(F;G): Problem 1.16 Let (X;M;µ) be a measure space. A set E ⊂ X is called locally measurable if E ∩ A ∈ M for all ˜ ˜ A∈Msuchthat µ(A)<∞. Let M be the collection of all locally measurable sets. Clearly M ⊂ M; ˜ if M = M, then µ is called saturated. a. If µ is σ-finite, then µ is saturated. ˜ b. M is a σ-algebra. ˜ c. Define µ˜ on M by µ˜(E) = µ(E) if E ∈ M and µ˜(E) = ∞ otherwise. Then µ˜ is a saturated ˜ measure on M, called the saturation of µ. d. If µ is complete, so is µ˜ ˜ e. Suppose that µ is semifinite. For E ∈ M, define µ(E) = sup{µ(A) : A ∈ M and A ⊂ E}. Then µ ˜ is a saturated measure on M that extends µ. f. Let X1;X2 be disjoint uncountable sets, X = X1 ∪ X2, and M the σ-algebra of count- able or co-countable sets in X. Let µ0 be the counting measure on P(X1), and define µ on M by ˜ µ(E) = µ0(E ∩ X1). Then µ is a measure on M, M = P(X), and in the notation of parts (c) and (e), µ˜ 6= µ. 2 Solution: ˜ ∞ (a) Suppose µ is σ-finite. Let A ∈ M, and let X = ∪ E where E ∈M and µ(E )<∞. Notice j=1 j j j ∞ ! ∞ A=A∩ [E =[A∩E: j j j=1 j=1 Each E ∩A∈M since A is locally measurable, and since A is a countable union of these sets, we j ˜ have A ∈ M. Hence M ⊂ M and µ is saturated. ˜ (b) Let E ∈ M. Take any A ∈ M such that µ(A) < ∞. Then c c c c E ∩A=A∩(E∩A) =(A ∪(E∩A)) ∈M: c ˜ ∞ ˜ Hence E ∈ M. Next, consider ∪ E, where each E ∈ M. Then for all A ∈ M such that i=1 i i µ(A) < ∞, we have ∞ ! ∞ [E ∩A=[(E ∩A)∈M: i i i=1 i=1 ˜ Hence M is a σ-algebra. ˜ ˜ (c) We show µ˜ is a measure on M. We have µ˜ : M → [0;∞] and µ˜(∅) = µ(∅) = 0, so it only remains ∞ ˜ to show countable additivity. Let {E } denote a sequence of disjoint sets in M. We partition j j=1 ∞ ∞ ! ∞ ! [E = [A ∪ [F ; j j j j=1 j=1 j=1 where A ;F ∈ {E }∞ ∪{∅}, A ∈ M, and F ∈= M or F = ∅. By not selecting the same E twice, j j j j=1 j j j k we can make sure that the elements of {A ;A ;:::;F ;F ;:::} are all pairwise disjoint. 1 2 1 2 P P ∞ ∞ ∞ ∞ Case 1: ∪ F =∅. Then µ˜(∪ E)= µ(E ) = µ˜(E ). j=1 j j=1 j j=1 j j=1 j ∞ S S Case 2: ∪ F ∈= M. Then some E ∈= M, and µ˜(E ) = ∞. Furthermore, ( A)∪( F)∈= M: j=1 j k k j j indeed, if (SA )∪(SF ) ∈ M, then j j ∞ ∞ ∞ ∞ [F =((([A)∪([F))c∪([A))c∈M: j j j j j=1 j=1 j=1 j=1 Therefore, we have ∞ ∞ ! ∞ !! ∞ µ˜([E ) = µ˜ [A ∪ [F =∞=Xµ˜(E): j j j j j=1 j=1 j=1 j=1 3 Case 3: SF 6= ∅ and SF ∈ M. In this case we have j j ∞ ∞ ∞ µ˜([E )=Xµ(A )+µ([F ): j j j j=1 j=1 j=1 Hence we need to show that µ(SF ) = ∞. Suppose µ(SF ) < ∞. Choose F such that F 6= ∅. j j j j Then since F is locally measurable, we have j ∞ ! F =F ∩ [F ∈M: j j j j=1 This contradiction shows that µ˜(S∞ E ) ≥ µ(SF ) = ∞. Since there is some E ∈= M, we have j=1 j j k Pµ˜(E ) = ∞. j ˜ ˜ ˜ Wenowprove that µ˜ is saturated. Let E ⊂ X be such that E ∩A ∈ M when µ˜(A) < ∞. Choose ˜ A∈Msuchthatµ(A)<∞. Then µ˜(A) <∞, and hence E ∩A ∈ M. But then (E ∩A)∩A ∈ M. ˜ Therefore, E ∩A ∈ M and E ∈ M. It follows that µ˜ is saturated. ˜ (d) Suppose µ is complete. If E ∈ M is such that µ(E) = 0, then µ˜ < ∞ and hence E ∈ M. ˜ Therefore, for all A ⊂ E, we have A ∈ M by completeness of µ. Therefore, A ∈ M and µ˜ is complete. ˜ (e) We prove that µ is a measure on M. Since µ(∅) = µ(∅) = 0, it remains to show countable ˜ S additivity. Let {E } be a collection of disjoint sets, with E ∈ M. Let A ∈ M be such that A ⊂ E . j j j Case 1: µ(A) < ∞. Then ∞ ! ∞ ∞ µ(A) = µ [(A∩E) =Xµ(A∩E)≤Xµ(E): j j i j=1 j=1 j=1 ˜ ˜ Case 2: suppose µ(A) = ∞. By semifiniteness, for all c > 0 there exists A ⊂ A such that A ∈ M ˜ and µ(A) = c. (Indeed, this is the definition of semifinite in Royden. I do not remember if it is pointed out directly in Folland, but in any case it is not hard to prove from Folland’s definition.) By case 1, c ≤ Pµ(E ), so Pµ(E ) = ∞. i i Therefore, µ(A) ≤ P∞ µ(E ): Taking the supremum over all such A, we have j=1 i ∞ ! ∞ µ [E ≤Xµ(E): j j j=1 j=1 We now show the reverse inequality. By the definition of the supremum, there exists a sequence 4
no reviews yet
Please Login to review.