jagomart
digital resources
picture1_Kant's Theory Of Space And Non Euclidean Geometriepdf


 155x       Filetype PDF       File size 0.09 MB       Source: www.personal.ceu.hu


File: Kant's Theory Of Space And Non Euclidean Geometriepdf
kants theory of space and the non euclidean geometries in the transcendental exposition of the concept of space in the space section of the transcendental aesthetic kant argues that geometry ...

icon picture PDF Filetype PDF | Posted on 25 Jan 2023 | 2 years ago
Partial capture of text on file.
                    KANT’S THEORY OF SPACE AND THE NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRIES 
                
                
               In the transcendental exposition of the concept of space in the “Space” section of the 
               Transcendental Aesthetic Kant argues that “geometry is a science which determines the 
                                                    1
               properties of space synthetically and yet a priori” . Together with the claims from the 
               metaphysical exposition in the same section that space is not derived from any outer 
               experience but it is a pure intuition and necessary a priori representation that is given as 
               infinite magnitude, this builds up the general framework of the relation between space 
               and geometry in Critique of Pure Reason. For Kant there exists only one geometry and 
               this is the Euclidean geometry. On this basis runs what Friedman calls “the standard 
               modern complaint against Kant”, namely, that he did not make the crucial distinction 
               between pure geometry and applied geometry. Since pure geometry makes no appeal to 
               spatial intuition or other experience and since the truth of the axioms of the applied 
               geometry depends upon an interpretation in the physical world the question about which 
               axiomatic system, the pure or the applied one, is true is settled only by empirical 
               investigation2. This directly contradicts Kant’s fundamental claim that we can know the 
               proposition of the Euclidean geometry a priori. 
                    Major part in this complaint is played by appeal to the non-Euclidean geometries. 
               Historically, this was initiated by Helmholtz who argued that Kant’s theory of space is 
                                                                    3
               untenable in the light of the discovery of the non-Euclidean geometries . His line was 
               later forcefully supported by Paton, Russel, Carnap, Schlick and probably at most 
               Reichenbach, who famously criticized Kant’s conception of space on the basis of a 
               complex analysis of the visual a priori which he took to underlie Kant’s doctrine of 
               geometry4. Recently, Parsons refers to this line as “the most common objections to 
                                5
               Kant’s theory of space”  and concedes that Kantian could still accept some more 
                                                             th
               primitive geometrical properties (than those provided by the 5  postulate of Euclid’s 
               Elements, for example) to be known a priori even if he abandons the claim that in 
               specific propositions of the Euclidean geometry can be known a priori. Though this is an 
               attempt to salvage some part of the geometry doctrine I do not think that this is in the 
               spirit of the Transcendental Aesthetic and also, I believe that it would be insufficient for 
               Kant’s purposes. 
                    My aim in this paper will be defend the view that Kant’s doctrine of geometry can 
               survive criticism based on appeal to the non-Euclidean geometries. I will argue that we 
               can still make sense of Kant’s claim that it is the Euclidean geometry that determines the 
               properties of space and that it does it a priori provided that we have proper understanding 
               of his space conception as a pure form of the intuition. I will try to show that Kant’s 
               appeal to basic propositions of the Euclidean geometry as necessary true and intuitively 
               certain could still be defended. I will argue, partly in the sense of Friedman, that we do 
               not have to accept the pure – applied geometry distinction but my justification will not be 
               based on his interpretation of the connection between Kant’s logic and philosophy of 
               mathematics. I would rather argue that such distinction is inappropriately applied ad hoc 
               to the doctrine of space alone but its claim is of much bigger scope and as such should be 
               met by frontal debate against Kant’s system of transcendental idealism. Such debate, 
               however, often is either not offered by the critics or dissolves the strength of the criticism 
               upon much broader field. 
                                                                                    2 
                     If the distinction is dispensed in such way, most critiques based on appeal to the 
               non-Euclidean geometries will be reduced to the principle claim that the propositions of 
               the Euclidean geometry are not the only candidates for true with certainty any more but 
               the propositions of the non-Euclidean geometry are competitors as well. The common 
               reading of this claim is that the non-Euclidean propositions are also intuitable or 
               visualizable in our intuition, as such they could (alone or also) be true of it and therefore 
               the Euclidean ones are not apodeictic, necessary true and intuitively certain. I will claim 
               that the non-Euclidean propositions cannot be true of the space of the intuition since they 
               lack a set of substantial properties that are necessary for the space of the intuition and that 
               are actually found there upon introspection. I will argue that only the Euclidean geometry 
               provides these properties and as such it is indispensable for the space of the intuition not 
               only in the Kant’s but in a broader sense.  
                      
                                   PURE – APPLIED GEOMETRY DISTINCTION 
                
               Among the recent studies of the topic probably Friedman formulated most clearly this 
               objection, when he says that “Kant fails to make the crucial distinction between pure and 
               applied geometry”6. Interestingly, this approach has been used in both directions, as 
               criticism of Kant’s theory of space (Russell, Reichenbach, and Hopkins) but also as a 
               way to save the doctrine (Ewing, Strawson). The division gave birth to different 
               interpretations that multiplied the possible options among which we could choose from. 
                                                              7
               Thus Schiller divided the space to perceptual and conceptual , Craig proposed three 
               readings of what the geometrical axioms (the Euclidean ones) could be true of, the space 
                                                                                  8
               of sense-impressions, the space of mental images and the space of the way things look . 
               Lucas distinguished between four different senses of use of the word “space”: as a term 
               of the pure mathematics, as a term of the physics, as a space of our ordinary experience 
                                                                                 9
               and as a possibility for existence (construction) of objects (geometrical and physical) . 
               Satisfactory comment on all these readings is beyond the scope of the present discussion 
               but it is important to point that although all they have merits of their own yet some of 
               them fail to account properly for one but crucial aspect of space’s meaning in the 
                                                              10
               Critique of Pure Reason, namely that space is pure intuition  and was never meant to 
               apply to things in themselves.  Traditionally, this is the sense in which applied geometry 
               is interpreted and at present day most physicist regard the rules of geometry, whatever 
               they are as applied to the realm of the things as they are by themselves. Pure intuition, 
                                                                                  11
               however, is what provides for Kant immediate representation to objects for the subject  
               and which not only precedes the actual appearances of the objects but in fact makes them 
                     12
               possible . The term “pure” is clarified (in the transcendental sense) as “there is nothing 
               that belongs to sensation”.13 Together with the claim that “space does not represent any 
               property of things in themselves, nor does it represent them in their relation to one 
                      14
               another”  this implies that on the one hand the space notion Kant builds is not 
               determined by the experience but on the opposite, makes it possible and on the other hand 
               that has no claim whatsoever about the world of the things in themselves, what at present 
               day is meant under the term “physical world”.  
                     Proper understanding should recognize that the lack of epistemic access to the 
               world of the things in themselves is not simply due to the character of the space notion 
               but it is a fundamental feature of Kant’s epistemic and ontological model of the world. 
               Taking this into account any criticism against the non-applicability of the space to the 
                                                     3 
          physical world rush ahead and neglect the fact that such ambitious criticism is to be 
          targeted against the complete model instead. Since it is not that much of a criticism 
          against space that it is not applied to the physical world, the responsibility for the 
          application of space is dependent on the general model. In this sense it is not a deficiency 
          of Kant’s doctrine of space and geometry in particular whether it is or it could be true of 
          the physical world. The space notion and the role of geometry is to be understood 
          properly only within Kant’s system and within the system the notion of space is 
          consistent and even necessary for the lack of appeal to the physical world as such (an 
          sich). Any criticism against the big model, however, was rarely if at all presented as 
          accompanying talks about  space and geometry. In this sense, any objection of the 
          simplified form “Kant claims that the propositions of the Euclidean geometry are the only 
          true ones as describing space, our space is the physical space and not a subjective one, 
          there is physical geometry that actually describes the space truly and this geometry is 
          non-Euclidean, therefore Kant’s theory of space and geometry is wrong” is without the 
          necessary back up, namely, the very reason why Kant is wrong when he says that we do 
          not know the things in themselves but only as they appear to us. Such criticism, however, 
          becomes much more complicated than the relatively simple discussion about space and 
          geometry and since it would position itself within centuries of unresolved philosophical 
          debates it is much less obvious than the ad hoc objections about geometry. It is not 
          surprising that most critics prefer to attack the concrete issue and avoid more 
          fundamental debate. However, no such approach could be entirely successful since it 
          does not explain why we should prefer, for example, direct realism about the external 
          world instead a representational theory of the kind proposed by Kant. I believe that mere 
          appeal for skeptical implausibility about external world as feature of Kant’s general 
          model will not do the job, at least with respect to space and geometry. Without successful 
          final of frontal criticism against the general model there is no justification for introducing 
          “applied geometry” as an option of a distinction as it is meant to apply to the world of the 
          things in themselves at all. This would, however, undermine the reasons for introducing 
          the distinction with respect to Kant’s theory of space and geometry. 
             As an illustration, often the objection about the non-applicability of geometry to 
          the physical world takes the following form, the example here being taken from Russell: 
           
          On the other hand there is geometry as a branch of physics, as it appears, for example, in the general theory 
          of relativity; this is an empirical science, in which the axioms are inferred from measurements and are 
          found to differ from Euclid’s. Thus …. it is synthetic but not a priori15. 
           
          There are two difficulties for Kant here: one about the a posteriori character of the 
          axioms and another (an implicit one) that the Euclidean geometry is not true as applied to 
          the physical world. Response to this could be the following: even if the large scale of the 
          universe is properly described according to the general theory of relativity by a spherical 
          geometry the scale of the ordinary human experience is still almost complete 
          approximation of the Euclidean geometry. The differences are so minute that they are 
          practically undistinguishable. In this sense the Euclidean geometry is still true when 
          applied to some scales and definitely true when applied to the human scale ordinary 
          experience.  Further, for Kant the question would not be that much if the geometry is 
          applied to the world of the things in themselves since this option is ruled out in general 
          but whether this geometry is true of how the world appears to us. Here, the supposition 
                                                                 4 
            that this is a non-Euclidean geometry is not obvious at all. Later in the paper I will argue 
            that practically the geometry of the space of the intuition is Euclidean and cannot be non-
            Euclidean. Nevertheless all this is more or less irrelevant for Kant’s space doctrine since 
            the physical geometry and the pure one would coincide in his system. There will be only 
            one geometry in and this would be the geometry that reigns the space of the intuition. 
            This is Strawson’s point in The Bounds of Sense when he comments on the traditional 
            criticism: 
             
            He thought that the geometry of the physical space had to be identical with the geometry of the 
            phenomenal space. And this mystery does invite the suggestion that the geometry of the phenomenal space 
            embodies, as it were, conditions under which alone things can count as things in space, as physical objects, 
            for us. Especially does it invite this suggestion if we think of something’s counting as a physical body for 
            us in terms of it’s appearing to us, presenting to a phenomenal figure …16 
             
            This geometry is not related to the world of the things in themselves at all, it prescribes 
            (geometrical) predicates only as far as the objects appear to us.17 Also, even if this 
            geometry happens to be non-Euclidean one this still does not mean that it is a posteriori 
            since, as Jones points  
             
            Nor did Gauss, Lobachevski, or Bolyai follow such (empirical, my note) procedure in developing non-
            Euclidean geometry. They all carried out their work without recourse to experience, and thus a priori. Just 
            what their criterions of truth need not be considered here, but they certainly were not empirical …18  
                                          
            So, after the claim that geometry must describe the physical world as such is dismissed 
            the argument against apriority of the axioms could be met by simple appeal to the history 
            of the development of the non-Euclidean geometries and the foundations of their axioms. 
            A weaker variation of criticism based on non-Euclidean geometries says that since Kant 
            affirmed that only one geometry is true of the intuitive space the very discovery of the 
            alternative geometries proved him wrong. This could be met by pointing that Kant 
                                  19
            actually anticipated such possibilities  and that the question is reduced to the next one 
            whether the geometries are and could be intuitively true. As I mentioned above, this 
            question will be discussed further in the paper. 
                To sum up, an attempt to criticize Kant’s theory of space on the basis that he did 
            not distinguished between pure and applied geometry could not be successful since the 
            question of what does the space apply to with Kant is resolved by appeal to the world as 
            it appears to us. Whatever this world looks like, certain geometry is applied to it and the 
            question why this geometry is not applied to the world of the things in themselves is 
            meaningless for Kant since the only thing we can know about such world is that it exists 
            and no geometrical predicate can be applied to it or to its objects and the relations 
            between them. The further question about the status of the non-Euclidean geometries is 
            thus reduced to the question whether they apply to the space of the intuition and how. In 
            addition, an important explanatory remark in this respect is the point made by Friedman 
            who argues convincingly that the distinction between pure and applied geometry goes 
            together with certain understanding of logic that was not available to Kant since appears 
            with Gottlob’s Frege Begriffsschrift in 1879.20 The importance of this relation is, as 
                                        21      22
            Friedman stresses, also supported by Hintikka  and Parsons . 
                                          
                                          
The words contained in this file might help you see if this file matches what you are looking for:

...Kants theory of space and the non euclidean geometries in transcendental exposition concept section aesthetic kant argues that geometry is a science which determines properties synthetically yet priori together with claims from metaphysical same not derived any outer experience but it pure intuition necessary representation given as infinite magnitude this builds up general framework relation between critique reason for there exists only one on basis runs what friedman calls standard modern complaint against namely he did make crucial distinction applied since makes no appeal to spatial or other truth axioms depends upon an interpretation physical world question about axiomatic system true settled by empirical investigation directly contradicts fundamental claim we can know proposition major part played historically was initiated helmholtz who argued untenable light discovery his line later forcefully supported paton russel carnap schlick probably at most reichenbach famously criticize...

no reviews yet
Please Login to review.